-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 1
/
Seminar 9-Incomplete information in Static Games.tex
764 lines (526 loc) · 23.8 KB
/
Seminar 9-Incomplete information in Static Games.tex
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
\documentclass{article}
\usepackage[utf8]{inputenc}
\usepackage[T1]{fontenc}
\usepackage[english]{babel}
\setlength{\parindent}{0pt}
\usepackage{hyperref}
\hypersetup{
colorlinks=true,
linkcolor=blue,
filecolor=magenta,
urlcolor=cyan}
\usepackage{graphicx}
\graphicspath{ {./pic/} }
\usepackage{multicol}
\usepackage{lscape}
\usepackage{fourier,amssymb,microtype,amsmath,gensymb}
\newcommand{\R}{\mathbb{R}}
\usepackage{mdframed,caption,xcolor}
\usepackage{tikz,tkz-euclide}
\title{Seminar 9.Incomplete information in Static Games}
\author{Xiaoguang Ling \\ \href{[email protected]}{[email protected]}}
\date{\today}
\begin{document}
\maketitle
%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%
\section{Problem 1 - Bayesian normal form and NE}
Consider the following two normal form games. Assume that \textbf{only player $1$ knows} which game is being played, while player $2$ thinks that the two games are \textbf{equally likely}.\vspace{-21pt}
\begin{center}
Game $1$ \vspace{6pt}
$
\begin{array}{c|c|c|}
& L & R \\
\hline
U & 0,0 & 4,2 \\
\hline
D & 2,6 & 0,8 \\
\hline
\end{array}
$
\end{center}
\begin{center}
Game $2$ \vspace{6pt}
$
\begin{array}{c|c|c|}
& L & R \\
\hline
U' & 0,2 & 0,0 \\
\hline
D' & 2,0 & 2,2 \\
\hline
\end{array}
$
\end{center}
%***************************************************
\subsection*{(a) Bayesian normal form}
Model this situation in an \textit{ex ante} perspective by specifying the Bayesian normal form.
\begin{mdframed}[backgroundcolor=blue!20,linecolor=white]
Who has contingent strategies?
\begin{itemize}
\item Player 1 has private information (Game 1 or Game 2 is played), therefore has $2 \times 2 = 4$ types of contingent strategies,
\item Player 2 doesn't know either which game is played (incomplete) or how player 1 moves (static), thus can only choose $L$ or $R$.
\end{itemize}
\end{mdframed}
\begin{center}
$
\begin{array}{c|c|c|}
& L & R \\
\hline
UU' & 0,1 & 2,1 \\
\hline
UD' & 1,0 & 3,2 \\
\hline
DU' & 1,4 & 0,4 \\
\hline
DD' & 2,3 & 1,5 \\
\hline
\end{array}
$
\end{center}
%
\begin{mdframed}[backgroundcolor=blue!20,linecolor=white]
We calculate the payoff according to player 2's belief. For example, the
payoff for $(UU',L)$ is (0,1):
$$U^1= 0.5 \times 0 + 0.5 \times 0 =0$$
$$U^2= 0.5 \times 0 + 0.5 \times 2 =1$$
Note: the question is slightly different from those in Watson textbook.
\medskip
In the textbook, it often says
the nature moves with probability $(Pr_1,Pr_2)$, i.e. both of the two players can have expected payoff.
Here only player 2 has to guess, while player 1 doesn't need to.
\medskip
Although the question can be solved in the same way, you may wonder if it's reasonable to calculate player 1's "expected payoff" according to player 2's belief.
\medskip
\textbf{The payoff in the Bayesian noraml form is actually player 2's imagination.}
\begin{itemize}
\item Player 2 believes player 1 has the expected payoff $U^1 = 0.5 \times \cdots + 0.5 \times \cdots$, and player 1 knows what player 2 believes.
\item In the view of player 1, there is actually no expected payoff, since the which game to play is already determined for him/her.
\end{itemize}
We calculate player 1's "expected payoff" according to player 2's belief for 2 reasons:
\begin{itemize}
\item Player 2 believes player 1 has this payoff, and acts according to it. This will in return affect palyer 1's behavior.
\item Even though player 1's "expected payoff" is calcualted by $U^1 = 0.5 \times \cdots + 0.5 \times \cdots$, what it reflects is actually his/her peference given which game is played. For example:
\begin{itemize}
\item We know if Game 1 is played and player 2 chooses L, then $D \succsim U$ for player 1.
\item In the Bayesian normal form, this preference is reflected by: if player 2 chooses L, $DU' \succsim UU'$, $DD' \succsim UD'$, i.e. no matter $U'$ or $D'$ is chosen in Game 2, once Game 1 is played and player 2 chooses L, $D \succsim U$.
\end{itemize}
(Actually player 1's preference can be preserved by any belief ($0<Pr<1$) of player 2. )
\end{itemize}
Anyway, the method is the same, simply calculate the expected payoff according to the belief for both of the two players.
\end{mdframed}
%***************************************************
\subsection*{(b) NE}
For the Bayesian normal form found in part (a), determine a NE. Is there more than one NE?
\bigskip
\begin{center}
\includegraphics[width=0.4\textwidth]{9.q1}
\vspace{2mm}
\end{center}
\medskip
$(UD',R)$ is the unique NE.
\begin{mdframed}[backgroundcolor=blue!20,linecolor=white]
$UD'$ dominates $UU'$; $DD'$ dominates $DU'$ $\Rightarrow \ R$ dominates $L \ \Rightarrow \ UD'$ dominates $DD'$.
\medskip
Dominated strategies can't be BR and should be assigned with probability 0 (no mixed-strategy NE).
\end{mdframed}
%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%
\section{Problem 2 - Bayesian normal form}
Consider the following two variants of a battle-of-the-sexes game. The game at the top --
variant (i) -- is of the usual kind where both players wish to meet each other, while the one
at the bottom -- variant (ii) -- has the unusual feature that $1$ wishes to avoid 2.\vspace{-6pt}
% \begin{center}
% Variant (i) \vspace{6pt}
% $
% \begin{array}{c|c|c|}
% & O & M \\
% \hline
% O & 3,1 & 0,0 \\
% \hline
% M & 0,0 & 1,3 \\
% \hline
% \end{array}
% $
% \end{center}
% \begin{center}
% Variant (ii) \vspace{6pt}
% $
% \begin{array}{c|c|c|}
% & O & M \\
% \hline
% O' & 0,1 & 3,0 \\
% \hline
% M' & 1,0 & 0,3 \\
% \hline
% \end{array}
% $
% \end{center}
\begin{center}
\includegraphics[width=0.4\textwidth]{9.q2}
\vspace{2mm}
\end{center}
%
\subsection*{(a) NE - static \& complete information}
For each of these games, determine the set of (pure) rationalizable strategies for each
player, and the set of pure-strategy and/or mixed-strategy NE.
\bigskip
All strategies are rationalizable.
\begin{mdframed}[backgroundcolor=blue!20,linecolor=white]
Recall: Rationalizable strategies(Watson pp.70): The set of strategies that
survive iterated dominance is therefore called the rationalizable strategies.
Here all strategies can be BR (= UD for 2-player games).
\end{mdframed}
\textbf{Variant (i)} has 2 pure NE $(O,O)$, $(M,M)$, and a mixed NE $\left( \left( \tfrac34, \tfrac14 \right), \left( \tfrac14, \tfrac34 \right) \right)$ .
\medskip
To derive the mixed-strategy NE, let $p$ be the probability of $P_1$ choosing $O$ and $q$ be the probability of $P_2$ choosing $O$.
$$U^1_O=3q$$
$$U^1_M=1-q$$
$$U^1_O = U^1_M \Rightarrow 3q = 1-q \Rightarrow q = \tfrac14$$
$$U^2_O=p$$
$$U^2_M=3(1-q)$$
$$U^2_O = U^2_M \Rightarrow p = 3(1-p) \Rightarrow p = \tfrac34)$$
\bigskip
\textbf{Variant (ii)} has no pure NE but a mixed NE $\left( \left( \tfrac34, \tfrac14 \right), \left( \tfrac34, \tfrac14 \right) \right)$.
\medskip
To derive the mixed-strategy NE in variant (ii), let $p$ the probability of $1$ choosing $O'$ and $q$ being the probability of $2$ choosing $O$.
$$U^1_O=3(1-q)$$
$$U^1_M=q$$
$$U^1_O = U^1_M \Rightarrow 3(1-q) = q \Rightarrow q = \tfrac34$$
$$U^2_O=p$$
$$U^2_M=3(1-p)$$
$$U^2_O = U^2_M \Rightarrow p = 3(1-p) \Rightarrow p = \tfrac34$$
\begin{mdframed}[backgroundcolor=blue!20,linecolor=white]
Recall: why players are indifferent between O and M in a Mixed strategy?
\end{mdframed}
%***************************************************
\subsection*{(b) Bayesian normal form}
Assume next that only player $1$ knows which game is being played, while player $2$ thinks that
the two games are equally likely. Model this situation in an \textit{ex ante} perspective by specifying
the Bayesian normal form.
\smallskip
\begin{mdframed}[backgroundcolor=blue!20,linecolor=white]
Think: Who has private information and therefore contingent strategies?
\medskip
Payoff is calculated similarly to Question 1. For example, for $(OO',O)$ is $(\tfrac32,1)$:
$$U^1 = 0.5 \times 3 + 0.5 \times 0 = \tfrac32$$
$$U^2 = 0.5 \times 1 + 0.5 \times 1 = 1$$
\end{mdframed}
\begin{center}
$
\begin{array}{c|c|c|}
& O & M \\
\hline
OO' & \tfrac32,1 & \tfrac32,0 \\
\hline
OM' & 2,\tfrac12 & 0,\tfrac32 \\
\hline
MO' & 0,\tfrac12 & 2,\tfrac32 \\
\hline
MM' & \tfrac12,0 & \tfrac12,3 \\
\hline
\end{array}
$
\end{center}
%
%***************************************************
\subsection*{(c) Rationalizable strategies and NE}
For the Bayesian normal form found in part (b), determine the set of
(pure) rationalizable strategies for each player, and the set of pure-strategy and/or
mixed-strategy NE.
\bigskip
$MM'$ is dominated by $OO'$.
All the other strategies are rationalizable.
\medskip
\textbf{Pure-strategy NE}: $(MO', M)$.
\medskip
For mixed stategy, $P_1$ can choose strategies among (note MM' is dominated and $Pr(MM')=0$):$\{OO' , OM' , MO'\}$.
\medskip
There are 4 possible combinations:
\begin{equation}
(1)
\begin{cases}
OO' \\ OM'
\end{cases}
\quad (2)
\begin{cases}
OM' \\ MO'
\end{cases}
\quad (3)
\begin{cases}
OO' \\ MO'
\end{cases}
\quad (4)
\begin{cases}
OO' \\ OM' \\ MO'
\end{cases}
\nonumber
\end{equation}
Let $q$ being the probability of $P_2$ choosing $O$.
\begin{align*}
U^1_{OO'} &= \tfrac32 q + \tfrac32 (1-q) = \tfrac32 \\
U^1_{OM'} &= 2 q + 0 \times (1-q) = 2q \\
U^1_{MO'} &= 0 \times q + 2 (1-q) = 2 (1-q) \\
\end{align*}
\medskip
\textbf{(1)} If $P_1$ mixes $OO'$ and $OM'$ with probability $(p,1-p)$, i.e. player 2 has belief $(p,1-p,0,0)$.
\medskip
For $P_1$:
$$U^1_{OO'} = U^1_{OM'} \Rightarrow \tfrac32 = 2q \Rightarrow q =\tfrac34$$
For $P_2$:
\begin{align*}
U^2_{O} &= p + \tfrac12 (1-p) \\
U^2_{M} &= 0 \times p + \tfrac32 (1-p) = \tfrac32 (1-p) \\
U^2_{O} &= U^2_{M} \Rightarrow p + \tfrac12 (1-p) = \tfrac32 (1-p) \Rightarrow p=\tfrac12
\end{align*}
The NE is :$[\left( \tfrac12, \tfrac12, 0, 0 \right), \left( \tfrac34, \tfrac14 \right)]$
\begin{mdframed}[backgroundcolor=blue!20,linecolor=white]
Note how we assign 0 probability to the strategies $P_1$ doesn't choose.
\end{mdframed}
\textbf{(2)} If $P_1$ mixes $OM'$ and $MO'$ with probability $(p,1-p)$, i.e. player 2 has belief $(0,p,1-p,0)$.
\medskip
For $P_2$, facing with $P_1$'s mixed strategy, $M$ dominates $O$ (therefore $q=1$).
The mixed strategy brokes down (player 2's belief $(0,p,1-p,0)$ is not reasonable).
\medskip
\textbf{(3)} If $P_1$ mixes $OO'$ and $MO'$ with probability $(p,1-p)$, i.e. player 2 has belief $(p,0,1-p,0)$.
\medskip
For $P_1$:
$$U^1_{OO'} = U^1_{MO'} \Rightarrow \tfrac32 = 2 (1-q) \Rightarrow q =\tfrac14$$
For $P_2$:
\begin{align*}
U^2_{O} &= p + \tfrac12 (1-p) \\
U^2_{M} &= 0 \times p + \tfrac32 (1-p) = \tfrac32 (1-p) \\
U^2_{O} &= U^2_{M} \Rightarrow p + \tfrac12 (1-p) = \tfrac32 (1-p) \Rightarrow p=\tfrac12 \\
\end{align*}
The NE is :$[\left( \tfrac12, 0, \tfrac12, 0 \right), \left( \tfrac14, \tfrac34 \right)]$
\medskip
\textbf{(4)} If $P_1$ mixes $OO'$, $OM'$ and $MO'$ with probability $(m,n,1-m-n)$, i.e. player 2 has belief $(m,n,1-m-n,0)$.
\medskip
There must be $U^1_{OO'} = U^1_{OM'} = U^1_{MO'}$.
From (1) and (3) we already know
$P_2$'s belief supporting $U^1_{OO'} = U^1_{OM'}$ is different from his/her belief supporting
$U^1_{OO'} = U^1_{MO'}$. Therefore there is no such a brief that supports
$U^1_{OO'} = U^1_{OM'} = U^1_{MO'}$ simultaneously.
\medskip
\textbf{Mixed-stategy NE}: $\left( \left( \tfrac12, \tfrac12, 0, 0 \right), \left( \tfrac34, \tfrac14 \right) \right)$, and $\left( \left( \tfrac12, 0, \tfrac12, 0 \right), \left( \tfrac14, \tfrac34 \right) \right)$
\newpage
%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%
\section{Problem 3 - Rationalizability in incomplete information games}
(Watson Exercise 26.3, solution is on pp.~469-470)
Suppose that nature selects A with probability $1/2$ and B with probability
$1/2$. If nature selects A, then players $1$ and $2$ interact according to matrix
``A.'' If nature selects B, then the players interact according to matrix ``B.''
These matrices are pictured here. Suppose that, before the players select
their actions, player $1$ observes nature's choice. That is, \textbf{player $1$ knows
from which matrix the payoffs are drawn}, and player $1$ can condition his
or her decision on this knowledge. Player $2$ does not know which matrix is
being played when he or she selects between L and R.
\begin{center}
\includegraphics[width=0.7\textwidth]{9.q26_3}
\end{center}
\vspace{2mm}
\subsection*{(a) Representation, rationalizability and NE}
\textbf{(1) Draw the extensive-form and Bayesian normal form. }
\begin{center}
\includegraphics[width=0.9\textwidth]{9.q26_3_a}
\end{center}
\begin{mdframed}[backgroundcolor=blue!20,linecolor=white]
Note, the dashed line passes through all the four nodes, meaning player 2 doesn't know either which game is played (incomplete) or how player 1 moves (static), thus can only choose $L$ or $R$.
\end{mdframed}
\textbf{(2) Compute the set of rationalizable strategies and NE}
\begin{center}
\includegraphics[width=0.3\textwidth]{9.q26_3_b3}
\end{center}
$UU'$ is dominated by $DD'$, then $L$ is dominated by $R$. In the end, only $(DU',R)$ survives iterated dominance method.
\vspace{1mm}
Therefore the set of rationalizable strategies is $\{(DU',R)\}$. The only NE is $(DU',R)$
\subsection*{(b) A three-player interpretation }
Consider a three-player interpretation of this strategic setting in which each of player 1's types is modeled as a separate player. That is, the
game is played by players 1A, 1B, and 2. Assume that player 1A's
payoff is zero whenever nature chooses B; likewise, player 1B's payoff
is zero whenever nature selects A. Depict this version of the game in the
\textbf{extensive form} (remember that payoff vectors consist of three numbers)
and in the \textbf{normal form}. Compute the set of \textbf{rationalizable strategies and
find the NE}.
\vspace{1mm}
Extensive form:
\begin{center}
\includegraphics[width=0.67\textwidth]{9.q26_3_b1}
\end{center}
\vspace{2mm}
\begin{mdframed}[backgroundcolor=blue!20,linecolor=white]
Player 2 doesn't know who he/she is playing with.
\vspace{2mm}
Note also when Player 1A (1B) is reached, the payoff for 1B (1A) is 0 (in red frame).
\end{mdframed}
\vspace{4mm}
Normal form:
\begin{center}
\includegraphics[width=0.7\textwidth]{9.q26_3_b2}
\end{center}
\vspace{2mm}
\begin{mdframed}[backgroundcolor=blue!20,linecolor=white]
Although there are 3 players, player 2 still doesn't know who he/she is playing with. As a result, the payoff is in player 2's imagination, and player $1A$,$1B$ know how player 2 thinks clearly (an \textit{ex ante} perspective). For example,
$$U^{1A}_{D,U',R} = 0.5 \times 4 + 0.5 \times 0 =2$$
$$U^{1B}_{D,U',R} = 0.5 \times 0 + 0.5 \times 2 =1$$
$$U^{2}_{D,U',R} = 0.5 \times 4 + 0.5 \times 0 =2$$
\medskip
You can also draw the normal form the way on Geir's slides (lecture part 5, pp.5), i.e. draw
the matrix for player $1B$ and player $2$, and player $1A$ joins as another player.
\begin{itemize}
\item We use the textbook's way because it explains the next question more clearly,
\item Note also the difference between the textbook and Geir's slides:
\begin{itemize}
\item The textbook calculates expected payoff for all the 3 players, It's more intuitive and can get the correct Bayesian NE.
\item The slides pp.5 is an \textit{ex post} perspective, and the payoff for player $1A$ and $1B$ is not expected payoff but what they can really get.
\item More about \textit{ex post} and \textit{ex ante} perspective can be found \href{https://www.cs.toronto.edu/~cebly/2534/Notes/CSC2534_Lecture9.pdf}{here}.
\end{itemize}
\end{itemize}
\end{mdframed}
\subsubsection*{Rationalizable strategies}
\vspace{1mm}
\textbf{For player $1A$ and $1B$:}
If player $2$ choose $L$, $D'$ dominates $U'$, and $U$ dominates $D$. (($U$,$D'$) survives iterated dominance)
If player $2$ choose $R$, $D$ dominates $U$, and $U'$ dominates $D'$. (($D$,$U'$) survives iterated dominance)
As a result, all the strategies for $1A$ and $1B$ can be BR.
\medskip
\textbf{For Player $2$:}
Neither $L$ nor $R$ is dominated by the other action. Therefore both of the two
actions are rationalizable.
\medskip
\textbf{In conclusion}: the rationalizable strategy set is: $\{(U,D),(U',D'),(L,R)\}$.
\subsubsection*{Find the NE}
By backward induction, if player $2$ chooses $L$, the payoff is $1$ (by $(U,D',L)$); if player $2$ chooses $R$, the payoff is $2$ (by $(D,U',R)$). Thus player $2$ will choose $R$ and the NE is $(D,U',R)$.
\begin{mdframed}[backgroundcolor=blue!20,linecolor=white]
Note although player $2$ will only choose $R$ by backward induction, $R$ doesn't dominate $L$. Dominance means "always better no matter how the opponents act". Obviously, under some (non-NE) conditions $L$ yields more payoff than $R$.
\end{mdframed}
\subsection*{(c) 2-player view \& 3-player view}
Explain why the predictions of parts (a) and (b) are the same in regard
to equilibrium but different in regard to rationalizability. (Hint: The
answer has to do with the scope of the players' beliefs.)
\begin{mdframed}[backgroundcolor=blue!20,linecolor=white]
In the Bayesian normal form (in part(a)), $DD'$ strictly dominates $UU'$. That means that $DD'$ is better than $UU'$ independently of what beliefs player $1$ has about the choice of player 2.
This is true because player $1$ is one person and has a coherently belief.
\medskip
If we use the view of 3 players, then palyer $1$ are 2 different people, then $(DD',L)$ means both player $1A$ and player $1B$ think player $2$ will choose $L$, and $(DD',R)$ means both player $1A$ and $1B$ think player 2 will choose $R$.
\medskip
What if player $1A$ and player $1B$ have different beliefs? For example, player $1A$ believes player $2$ chooses $L$, then $U$ is prefered; and at the same time, player $1B$ believes player $2$ chooses $R$, then $U'$ is prefered.
\medskip
In this case, (U,U') is chosen separetely, not dominated!
\medskip
This belief separation doesn't affect NE because both player $1A$ and player $1B$ must agree that by backward induction, player $2$ will choose $R$.
\end{mdframed}
In part (b), the beliefs of players $1A$ and $1B$ do not have to
coincide, so they may end up making $U$ and $U'$ as rational choices based on their separated beliefs. While in NE, the beliefs of player $1A$ and $1B$ are the same (by backward induction).
%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%
\section{Problem 4 - Differentiated duopoly}
(Watson Exercise 26.5, solution is on pp.~470.)
Consider a differentiated duopoly market in which firms compete by selecting
prices and produce to fill orders. Let $p_1$ be the price chosen by firm
1 and let $p_2$ be the price of firm 2. Let $q_1$ and $q_2$ denote the quantities demanded
(and produced) by the two firms. Suppose that the demand for firm
1 is given by $q_1 = 22 - 2p_1 + p_2$ , and the demand for firm $2$ is given by
$q_2 = 22 - 2p_2 + p_1$ . Firm $1$ produces at a constant marginal cost of 10 and
no fixed cost. Firm $2$ produces at a constant marginal cost of c and no fixed
cost. The payoffs are the firms' individual profits.
\subsection*{(a) Payoff functions} The firms' strategies are their prices. Represent the normal form by writing the firms' payoff functions.
\begin{align*}
U^1 &= p_1 q_1 - 10 q_1 \\
&= p_1(22 - 2p_1 + p_2) -10(22 - 2p_1 + p_2) \\
&= 22P_1 -2p_1^2 + p_1p_2 - 220 + 20p_1 -10p_2 \\
&= -2p_1^2 +p_1p_2 + 42p_1 - 10p_2 -220\\
\\
U^2 &= p_2 q_2 - c q_2 \\
&= p_1(22 - 2p_2 + p_1) -c(22 - 2p_2 + p_1) \\
&= 22P_2 -2p_2^2 + p_1p_2 - 22c + 2cp_2 -cp_1 \\
&= -2p_2^2 +p_1p_2 -cp_1 + (22+2c)p_2 -22c
\end{align*}
\subsection*{(b) Calculate the firms' best-response functions.}
FOC:
$$\frac{\partial U^1}{\partial p_1} = 0 \Rightarrow -4p^*_1+42+p_2 = 0 \Rightarrow p^*_1 = \frac{42+p_2}{4}$$
SOC:
$$\frac{\partial^2 U^1}{\partial p^2_1} = -4 <0$$
FOC:
$$\frac{\partial U^2}{\partial p_2} = 0 \Rightarrow -4p^*_2+22+2c+p_1 = 0 \Rightarrow p^*_2 = \frac{22+2c+p_1}{4}$$
SOC:
$$\frac{\partial^2 U^2}{\partial p^2_2} = -4 <0$$
\begin{mdframed}[backgroundcolor=blue!20,linecolor=white]
For payoff functions, we use FOC \& SOC to find the BR functions. Be clear about what is variable an what is parameter. See also seminar 7 problem 3.
\end{mdframed}
\subsection*{(c) Complete information} Suppose that $c = 10$ so the firms are identical (the game is symmetric). Calculate the NE prices.
\medskip
When $c = 10$, we have:
\begin{align*}
p^*_1 = \frac{42+p_2}{4} \\
p^*_2 = \frac{42+p_1}{4}
\end{align*}
NE is a price s.t. both of the two firms are applying BR and there is no incentive to devicate.
That is, $p^*_1 = \frac{42+p^*_2}{4} =\frac{42+\frac{42+p_1}{4}}{4}$ (or $p^*_2 = \frac{42+p^*_1}{4}$).
Therefore $p^*_1 = p^*_2 =14$.
\subsection*{(d) Incomplete information} Now suppose that firm $1$ does not know firm 2's marginal cost c. With
probability $1/2$ nature picks $c = 14$, and with probability 1/2 nature
picks $c = 6$. \textbf{Firm $2$ knows} its own cost (that is, it observes nature's
move), but firm $1$ only knows that firm 2's marginal cost is either $6$ or
$14$ (with equal probabilities). Calculate the best-response functions of
player $1$ and the two types ($c = 6$ and $c = 14$) of player $2$ and calculate
the Bayesian NE quantities.
\bigskip
\begin{mdframed}[backgroundcolor=blue!20,linecolor=white]
With different MC, firm 2 can set different (contingent) price, while firm 1 can only set one price according to its expected payoff function.
\medskip
(Compare this with the extensive from games in this seminar. Always be clear about who has contingent strategies!)
\end{mdframed}
\textbf{For firm 2:}
\medskip
\textbf{$\quad $ (1) When $c=c^H=14$}
\smallskip
$\quad $(I omitted the superscript $^H$ of $p_2$ and $c$ for simpliciy. )
\begin{align*}
U^{2H} &= -2p_2^2 +p_1p_2 -cp_1 + (22+2c)p_2 -22c \quad \quad \text{(the result from question a.)} \\
&= -2p_2^2 +p_1p_2 -14p_1 + 50p_2 -22 \times 14
\end{align*}
$\quad $FOC:
$$\frac{\partial U^{2H}}{\partial p_2} = 0 \Rightarrow -4p^{H*}_2+ 50 + p_1 = 0 \Rightarrow p^{H*}_2 = \frac{50+p_1}{4}$$
$\quad $SOC:
$$\frac{\partial^2 U^{2H}}{\partial p^2_2} = -4 <0$$
\textbf{$\quad $(2)When $c=c^L=6$}
\smallskip
$\quad $ (I omitted the superscript $^L$ of $p_2$ and $c$ for simpliciy.)
\begin{align*}
U^{2L} &= -2p_2^2 +p_1p_2 -cp_1 + (22+2c)p_2 -22c \quad \quad \text{(the result from question a.)} \\
&= -2p_2^2 +p_1p_2 -6p_1 + 34p_2 -22 \times 6
\end{align*}
$\quad $FOC:
$$\frac{\partial U^{2L}}{\partial p_2} = 0 \Rightarrow -4p^{L*}_2+ 34 + p_1 = 0 \Rightarrow p^{L*}_2 = \frac{34+p_1}{4}$$
$\quad $SOC:
$$\frac{\partial^2 U^{2L}}{\partial p^2_2} = -4 <0$$
\textbf{For firm 1:}
\begin{align*}
E(U^1)&= 0.5 U^1(p_1,p_2^H) + 0.5 U^1(p_1,p_2^L) \\
&= 0.5(-2p_1^2 +p_1p^H_2 + 42p_1 - 10p^H_2 -220) + 0.5(-2p_1^2 +p_1p^L_2 + 42p_1 - 10p^L_2 -220)\\
&=-2p_1^2 + 42p_1 +(p_1 -10)(0.5p^H_2 + 0.5p^L_2) -220
\end{align*}
\begin{mdframed}[backgroundcolor=blue!20,linecolor=white]
Can we substitute firm 2's BR ($p^{H*}_2, p^{L*}_2$) into firm 1's expected utility function now? No! We want to get firm 1's BR to any ($p^H_2, p^L_2$), not just to firm 2's BR ($p^{H*}_2, p^{L*}_2$)!
\end{mdframed}
$\quad $FOC:
$$\frac{\partial U^{1}}{\partial p_1} = 0 \Rightarrow -4p^{*}_1+ 42 +(0.5p^H_2 + 0.5p^L_2) = 0 \Rightarrow p^{*}_1 = \frac{42 + 0.5(p^H_2 + p^L_2)}{4}$$
$\quad $SOC:
$$\frac{\partial^2 U^{1}}{\partial p^2_1} = -4 <0$$
\textbf{NE}: Denote the NE as $(p^*_1,p^{*H}_2,p^{*L}_2)$. The NE requires the BRs for the two firms achieved at the same time:
\begin{equation}
\begin{cases}
p^{H*}_2 = \frac{50+p^{*}_1}{4} \\
p^{L*}_2 = \frac{34+p^{*}_1}{4} \\
p^{*}_1 = \frac{42 + 0.5(p^{H*}_2 + p^{L*}_2)}{4}
\end{cases}
\nonumber
\end{equation}
(3 functions and 3 variables) solve by substitution,
$$p^{*}_1 = \frac{42 + 0.5(p^{*H}_2 + p^{*L}_2)}{4}= \frac{42 + 0.5(\frac{50+p^{*}_1}{4} + \frac{34+p^{*}_1}{4})}{4} $$
Therefore:
\begin{equation}
\begin{cases}
p^*_1 = 14 \\ p^{*H}_2 = 16 \\ p^{*L}_2 =12
\end{cases}
\nonumber
\end{equation}
\end{document}