-
-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 39
/
18-causality.Rmd
583 lines (364 loc) · 28.1 KB
/
18-causality.Rmd
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
# Causal Inference
After all of the mambo jumbo that we have learned so far, I want to now talk about the concept of causality. We usually say that correlation is not causation. Then, what is causation?\
One of my favorite books has explained this concept beautifully [@Pearl_2018]. And I am just going to quickly summarize the gist of it from my understanding. I hope that it can give you an initial grasp on the concept so that later you can continue to read up and develop a deeper understanding.
It's important to have a deep understanding regarding the method research. However, one needs to be aware of its limitation. As mentioned in various sections throughout the book, we see that we need to ask experts for number as our baseline or visit literature to gain insight from past research.
Here, we dive in a more conceptual side statistical analysis as a whole, regardless of particular approach.
You probably heard scientists say correlation doesn't mean causation. There are ridiculous [spurious correlations](http://www.tylervigen.com/spurious-correlations) that give a firm grip on what the previous phrase means. The pioneer who tried to use regression to infer causation in social science was @yule1899 (but it was a fatal attempt where he found relief policy increases poverty). To make a causal inference from statistics, **the equation (function form) must be stable** under intervention (i.e., variables are manipulated). Statistics is used to be a causality-free enterprise in the past.
Not until the development of path analysis by Sewall Wright in the 1920s that the discipline started to pay attention to causation. Then, it remained dormant until the Causal Revolution (quoted Judea Pearl's words). This revolution introduced the calculus of causation which includes (1) causal diagrams), and (2) a symbolic language
The world has been using $P(Y|X)$ (statistics use to derive this), but what we want is to compare the difference between
- $P(Y|do(X))$: treatment group
- $P(Y|do(not-X))$: control group
Hence, we can see a clear difference between $P(Y|X) \neq P(Y|do(X))$
The conclusion we want to make from data is counterfactuals: **What would have happened had we not do X?**
To teach a robot to make inference, we need inference engine
![p. 12 [@Pearl_2018]](images/Figure%20I.png "Inference Engine"){style="display: block; margin: 1em auto" width="600" height="400"}
Levels of cognitive ability to be a causal learner:
1. Seeing
2. Doing
3. Imagining
Ladder of causation (associated with levels of cognitive ability as well):
1. Association: conditional probability, correlation, regression
2. Intervention
3. Counterfactuals
+-----------------+-------------+-------------------------------------------+------------------------------------------------------------+
| Level | Activity | Questions | Examples |
+=================+=============+===========================================+============================================================+
| Association | Seeing | What is? | What does a symptom tell me about a disease? |
| | | | |
| $P(y|x)$ | | How would seeing X change my belief in Y? | |
+-----------------+-------------+-------------------------------------------+------------------------------------------------------------+
| Intervention | Doing | What if? | What if I spend more time learning, will my result change? |
| | | | |
| $P(y|do(x),z)$ | Intervening | What if I do X? | |
+-----------------+-------------+-------------------------------------------+------------------------------------------------------------+
| Counterfactuals | Imagining | Why?\ | What if I stopped smoking a year ago? |
| | | was it X that caused Y? | |
| $P(y_x|x',y')$ | | | |
| | | What if I had acted differently | |
+-----------------+-------------+-------------------------------------------+------------------------------------------------------------+
Table by [@pearl2019seven, p. 57]
You cannot define causation from probability alone
If you say X causes Y if X raises the probability of Y." On the surface, it might sound intuitively right. But when we translate it to probability notation: $P(Y|X) >P(Y)$ , it can't be more wrong. Just because you are seeing X (1st level), it **doesn't mean** the probability of Y increases.
It could be either that (1) X causes Y, or (2) Z affects both X and Y. Hence, people might use **control variables**, which translate: $P(Y|X, Z=z) > P(Y|Z=z)$, then you can be more confident in your probabilistic observation. However, the question is how can you choose $Z$
With the invention of the do-operator, now you can represent X causes Y as
$$
P(Y|do(X)) > P(Y)
$$
and with the help of causal diagram, now you can answer questions at the 2nd level (Intervention)
Note: people under econometrics might still use "Granger causality" and "vector autoregression" to use the probability language to represent causality (but it's not).
The 7 tools for Structural Causal Model framework [@pearl2019seven]:
1. Encoding Causal Assumptions - transparency and testability (with graphical representation)
2. Do-calculus and the control of confounding: "back-door"
3. The algorithmization of Counterfactuals
4. Mediation Analysis and the Assessment of Direct and Indirect Effects
5. Adaptability, External validity and Sample Selection Bias: are still researched under "domain adaptation", "transfer learning"
6. Recovering from missing data
7. Causal Discovery:
1. d-separation
2. Functional decomposition [@hoyer2008nonlinear]
3. Spontaneous local changes [@pearl2014graphical]
[List of packages to do causal inference](https://cran.r-project.org/web/views/CausalInference.html) in R
Simpson's Paradox:
- A statistical association seen in an entire population is reversed in sub-population.
Structural Causal Model accompanies graphical causal model to create more efficient language to represent causality
Structural Causal Model is the solution to the curse of dimensionality (i.e., large numbers of variable $p$, and small dataset $n$) thanks to product decomposition. It allows us to solve problems without knowing the function, parameters, or distributions of the error terms.
Suppose you have a causal chain $X \to Y \to Z$:
$$
P(X=x,Y=y, Z=z) = P(X=x)P(Y=y|X=x)P(Z=z|Y=y)
$$
+------------------------------------------------+-------------------------------------------------+
| Experimental Design | Quasi-experimental Design |
+================================================+=================================================+
| Experimentalist | Observationalist |
+------------------------------------------------+-------------------------------------------------+
| Experimental Data | Observational Data |
+------------------------------------------------+-------------------------------------------------+
| Random Assignment (reduce treatment imbalance) | Random Sampling (reduce sample selection error) |
+------------------------------------------------+-------------------------------------------------+
Criticisms of quasi-experimental versus experimental designs:
- Quasi-experimental methods don't approximate well experimental results. For example,
- @lalonde1986evaluating shows [Matching Methods], [Difference-in-differences], [Tobit-2] (Heckman-type) can't approximate the experimental estimates.
Tools in a hierarchical order
1. [Experimental Design]: Randomized Control Trials (Gold standard): Tier 1
2. [Quasi-experimental]
1. [Regression Discontinuity]
2. [Synthetic Difference-in-Differences]
3. [Difference-In-Differences]
4. [Synthetic Control]
5. [Event Studies]
6. Fixed Effects Estimator \@ref(fixed-effects-estimator)
7. [Endogenous Treatment]: mostly [Instrumental Variables]
8. [Matching Methods]
9. [Interrupted Time Series]
10. Endogenous Sample Selection \@ref(endogenous-sample-selection): mostly Heckman's correction
Internal vs. External Validity
- Internal Validity: Economists and applied scientists largely care about.
- External Validity: Localness might affect your external validity.
For many economic policies, there is a difference between **treatment** and **intention to treat**.
For example, we might have an effective vaccine (i.e., intention to treat), but it does not mean that everybody will take it (i.e., treatment).
There are four types of subjects that we deal with:
- **Non-switchers**: we don't care about non-switchers because even if we introduce or don't introduce the intervention, it won't affect them.
- **Always takers**
- **Never takers**
- **Switchers**
- **Compliers**: defined as those who respect the intervention.
- We only care about compliers because when we introduce the intervention, they will do something. When we don't have any interventions, they won't do it.
- Tools above are used to identify the causal impact of an intervention on compliers
- If we have only **compliers** in our dataset, then **intention to treatment = treatment effect**.
- **Defiers**: those who will go to the opposite direction of your treatment.
- We typically aren't interested in defiers because they will do the opposite of what we want them to do. And they are typically a small group; hence, we just assume they don't exist.
| | Treatment Assignment | Control Assignment |
|---------------|----------------------|--------------------|
| Compliers | Treated | No Treated |
| Always-takers | Treated | Treated |
| Never-takers | Not treated | No treated |
| Defiers | Not treated | Treated |
Directional Bias due to selection into treatment comes from 2 general opposite sources
1. **Mitigation-based**: select into treatment to combat a problem
2. **Preference-based**: select into treatment because units like that kind of treatment.
## Treatment effect types
This section is based on [Paul Testa's note](https://egap.org/resource/10-types-of-treatment-effect-you-should-know-about/)
Terminology:
- Quantities of causal interest (i.e., treatment effect types)
- Estimands: parameters of interest
- Estimators: procedures to calculate hesitates for the parameters of interest
Sources of bias ([according to prof. Luke Keele](https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=CjZnQ3ToJjg))
$$
\begin{aligned}
&\text{Estimator - True Causal Effect} \\
&= \text{Hidden bias + Misspecification bias + Statistical Noise} \\
&= \text{Due to design + Due to modeling + Due to finite sample}
\end{aligned}
$$
### Average Treatment Effects
Average treatment effect (ATE) is the difference in means of the treated and control groups
**Randomization** under [Experimental Design] can provide an unbiased estimate of ATE.
Let $Y_i(1)$ denote the outcome of individual $i$ under treatment and
$Y_i(0)$ denote the outcome of individual $i$ under control
Then, the treatment effect for individual $i$ is the difference between her outcome under treatment and control
$$
\tau_i = Y_i(1) - Y_i(0)
$$
Without a time machine or dimension portal, we can only observe one of the two event: either individual $i$ experiences the treatment or she doesn't.
Then, the ATE as a quantity of interest can come in handy since we can observe across all individuals
$$
ATE = \frac{1}{N} \sum_{i=1}^N \tau_i = \frac{\sum_1^N Y_i(1)}{N} - \frac{\sum_i^N Y_i(0)}{N}
$$
With random assignment (i.e., treatment assignment is independent of potential outcome and observables and unobservables), the observed means difference between the two groups is an unbiased estimator of the average treatment effect
$$
E(Y_i (1) |D = 1) = E(Y_i(1)|D=0) = E(Y_i(1)) \\
E(Y_i(0) |D = 1) = E(Y_i(0)|D = 0 ) = E(Y_i(0))
$$
$$
ATE = E(Y_i(1)) - E(Y_i(0))
$$
Alternatively, we can write the potential outcomes model in a regression form
$$
Y_i = Y_i(0) + [Y_i (1) - Y_i(0)] D_i
$$
Let $\beta_{0i} = Y_i (0) ; \beta_{1i} = Y_i(1) - Y_i(0)$, we have
$$
Y_i = \beta_{0i} + \beta_{1i} D_i
$$
where
- $\beta_{0i}$ = outcome if the unit did not receive any treatment
- $\beta_{1i}$ = treatment effect (i.e., random coefficients for each unit $i$)
To understand endogeneity (i.e., nonrandom treatment assignment), we can examine a standard linear model
$$
\begin{aligned}
Y_i &= \beta_{0i} + \beta_{1i} D_i \\
&= ( \bar{\beta}_{0} + \epsilon_{0i} ) + (\bar{\beta}_{1} + \epsilon_{1i} )D_i \\
&= \bar{\beta}_{0} + \epsilon_{0i} + \bar{\beta}_{1} D_i + \epsilon_{1i} D_i
\end{aligned}
$$
When you have random assignment, $E(\epsilon_{0i}) = E(\epsilon_{1i}) = 0$
- No selection bias: $D_i \perp e_{0i}$
- Treatment effect is independent of treatment assignment: $D_i \perp e_{1i}$
But otherwise, residuals can correlate with $D_i$
For estimation,
- $\hat{\beta}_1^{OLS}$ is identical to difference in means (i.e., $Y_i(1) - Y_i(0)$)
- In case of heteroskedasticity (i.e., $\epsilon_{0i} + D_i \epsilon_{1i} \neq 0$ ), this residual's variance depends on $X$ when you have heterogeneous treatment effects (i.e., $\epsilon_{1i} \neq 0$)
- Robust SE should still give consistent estimate of $\hat{\beta}_1$ in this case
- Alternatively, one can use two-sample t-test on difference in means with unequal variances.
### Conditional Average Treatment Effects
Treatment effects can be different for different groups of people. In words, treatment effects can vary across subgroups.
To examine the heterogeneity across groups (e.g., men vs. women), we can estimate the conditional average treatment effects (CATE) for each subgroup
$$
CATE = E(Y_i(1) - Y_i(0) |D_i, X_i))
$$
### Intent-to-treat Effects
When we encounter non-compliance (either people suppose to receive treatment don't receive it, or people suppose to be in the control group receive the treatment), treatment receipt is not independent of potential outcomes and confounders.
In this case, the difference in observed means between the treatment and control groups is not [Average Treatment Effects], but [Intent-to-treat Effects] (ITT). In words, ITT is the treatment effect on those who **receive** the treatment
### Local Average Treatment Effects
Instead of estimating the treatment effects of those who **receive** the treatment (i.e., [Intent-to-treat Effects]), you want to estimate the treatment effect of those who actually **comply** with the treatment. This is the local average treatment effects (LATE) or complier average causal effects (CACE). I assume we don't use CATE to denote complier average treatment effect because it was reserved for conditional average treatment effects.
- Using random treatment assignment as an instrument, we can recover the effect of treatment on compliers.
![](images/iv_late.PNG){width="600" height="360"}
- As the percent of compliers increases, [Intent-to-treat Effects] and [Local Average Treatment Effects] converge
- Rule of thumb: SE(LATE) = SE(ITT)/(share of compliers)
- LATE estimate is always greater than the ITT estimate
- LATE can also be estimated using a pure placebo group [@gerber2010].
- Partial compliance is hard to study, and IV/2SLS estimator is biased, we have to use Bayesian [@long2010; @jin2009; @jin2008].
#### One-sided noncompliance
- One-sided noncompliance is when in the sample, we only have compliers and never-takers
- With the exclusion restriction (i.e., excludability), never-takers have the same results in the treatment or control group (i.e., never treated)
- With random assignment, we can have the same number of never-takers in the treatment and control groups
- Hence,
$$
LATE = \frac{ITT}{\text{share of compliers}}
$$
#### Two-sided noncompliance
- Two-sided noncompliance is when in the sample, we have compliers, never-takers, and always-takers
- To estimate LATE, beyond excludability like in the [One-sided noncompliance] case, we need to assume that there is no defiers (i.e., monotonicity assumption) (this is excusable in practical studies)
$$
LATE = \frac{ITT}{\text{share of compliers}}
$$
### Population vs. Sample Average Treatment Effects
See [@imai2008] for when the sample average treatment effect (SATE) diverges from the population average treatment effect (PATE).
To stay consistent, this section uses notations from [@imai2008]'s paper.
In a finite population $N$, we observe $n$ observations ($N>>n$), where half is in the control and half is in the treatment group.
With unknown data generating process, we have
$$
I_i =
\begin{cases}
1 \text{ if unit i is in the sample} \\
0 \text{ otherwise}
\end{cases}
$$
$$
T_i =
\begin{cases}
1 \text{ if unit i is in the treatment group} \\
0 \text{ if unit i is in the control group}
\end{cases}
$$
$$
\text{potential outcome} =
\begin{cases}
Y_i(1) \text{ if } T_i = 1 \\
Y_i(0) \text{ if } T_i = 0
\end{cases}
$$
Observed outcome is
$$
Y_i | I_i = 1= T_i Y_i(1) + (1-T_i)Y_i(0)
$$
Since we can never observed both outcome for the same individual, the treatment effect is always unobserved for unit $i$
$$
TE_i = Y_i(1) - Y_i(0)
$$
Sample average treatment effect is
$$
SATE = \frac{1}{n}\sum_{i \in \{I_i = 1\}} TE_i
$$
Population average treatment effect is
$$
PATE = \frac{1}{N}\sum_{i=1}^N TE_i
$$
Let $X_i$ be observables and $U_i$ be unobservables for unit $i$
The baseline estimator for SATE and PATE is
$$
\begin{aligned}
D &= \frac{1}{n/2} \sum_{i \in (I_i = 1, T_i = 1)} Y_i - \frac{1}{n/2} \sum_{i \in (I_i = 1 , T_i = 0)} Y_i \\
&= \text{observed sample mean of the treatment group} \\
&- \text{observed sample mean of the control group}
\end{aligned}
$$
Let $\Delta$ be the estimation error (deviation from the truth), under an additive model
$$
Y_i(t) = g_t(X_i) + h_t(U_i)
$$
The decomposition of the estimation error is
$$
\begin{aligned}
PATE - D = \Delta &= \Delta_S + \Delta_T \\
&= (PATE - SATE) + (SATE - D)\\
&= \text{sample selection}+ \text{treatment imbalance} \\
&= (\Delta_{S_X} + \Delta_{S_U}) + (\Delta_{T_X} + \Delta_{T_U}) \\
&= \text{(selection on observed + selection on unobserved)} \\
&+ (\text{treatment imbalance in observed + unobserved})
\end{aligned}
$$
#### Estimation Error from Sample Selection
Also known as sample selection error
$$
\Delta_S = PATE - SATE = \frac{N - n}{N}(NATE - SATE)
$$
where NATE is the non-sample average treatment effect (i.e., average treatment effect for those in the population but not in your sample:
$$
NATE = \sum_{i\in (I_i = 0)} \frac{TE_i}{N-n}
$$
From the equation, to have zero sample selection error (i.e., $\Delta_S = 0$), we can either
- Get $N = n$ by redefining your sample as the population of interest
- $NATE = SATE$ (e.g., $TE_i$ is constant over $i$ in both your selected sample, and those in the population that you did not select)
Note
- When you have heterogeneous treatment effects, **random sampling** can only warrant **sample selection bias**, not **sample selection error**.
- Since we can rarely know the true underlying distributions of the observables ($X$) and unobservables ($U$), we cannot verify whether the empirical distributions of your observables and unobservables for those in your sample is identical to that of your population (to reduce $\Delta_S$). For special case,
- Say you have census of your population, you can adjust for the observables $X$ to reduce $\Delta_{S_X}$, but still you cannot adjust your unobservables ($U$)
- Say you are willing to assume $TE_i$ is constant over
- $X_i$, then $\Delta_{S_X} = 0$
- $U_i$, then $\Delta_{U}=0$
#### Estimation Error from Treatment Imbalance
Also known as treatment imbalance error
$$
\Delta_T = SATE - D
$$
$\Delta_T \to 0$ when treatment and control groups are balanced (i.e., identical empirical distributions) for both observables ($X$) and unobservables ($U$)
However, in reality, we can only readjust for observables, not unobservables.
+-------------------------------------------------------------+---------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------+-----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------+
| | [Blocking][Randomized Block Designs] | **[Matching Methods]** |
+=============================================================+=================================================================================================================================================================================+===============================================================================================================================================================================================================================================+
| Definition | Random assignment within strata based on pre-treatment observables | Dropping, repeating or grouping observations to balance covariates between the treatment and control group [@rubin1973use] |
+-------------------------------------------------------------+---------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------+-----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------+
| Time | Before randomization of treatments | After randomization of treatments |
+-------------------------------------------------------------+---------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------+-----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------+
| What if the set of covariates used to adjust is irrelevant? | Nothing happens | In the worst case scenario (e.g., these variables are uncorrelated with the treatment assignment, but correlated with the post-treatment variables), matching induces bias that is greater than just using the unadjusted difference in means |
+-------------------------------------------------------------+---------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------+-----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------+
| Benefits | $\Delta_{T_X}=0$ (no imbalance on observables). But we don't know its effect on unobservables imbalance (might reduce if the unobservables are correlated with the observables) | Reduce model dependence, bias, variance, mean-square error |
+-------------------------------------------------------------+---------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------+-----------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------+
### Average Treatment Effects on the Treated and Control
Average Effect of treatment on the Treated (ATT) is
$$
\begin{aligned}
ATT &= E(Y_i(1) - Y_i(0)|D_i = 1) \\
&= E(Y_i(1)|D_i = 1) - E(Y_i(0) |D_i = 1)
\end{aligned}
$$
Average Effect of treatment on the Control (ATC) (i.e., the effect **would be** for those weren't treated) is
$$
\begin{aligned}
ATC &= E(Y_i(1) - Y_i (0) |D_i =0) \\
&= E(Y_i(1)|D_i = 0) - E(Y_i(0)|D_i = 0)
\end{aligned}
$$
Under random assignment and full compliance,
$$
ATE = ATT = ATC
$$
**Sample average treatment effect on the treated** is
$$
SATT = \frac{1}{n} \sum_i TE_i
$$
where
- $TE_i$ is the treatment effect for unit $i$
- $n$ is the number of treated units in the sample
- $i$ belongs the subset (i.e., sample) of the population of interest that is treated.
**Population average treatment effect on the treated** is
$$
PATT = \frac{1}{N} \sum_i TE_i
$$
where
- $TE_i$ is the treatment effect for unit $i$
- $N$ is the number of treated units in the population
- $i$ belongs to the population of interest that is treated.
### Quantile Average Treatment Effects
Instead of the middle point estimate (ATE), we can also understand the changes in the distribution the outcome variable due to the treatment.
Using quantile regression and more assumptions [@abadie2002instrumental; @chernozhukov2005iv], we can have consistent estimate of quantile treatment effects (QTE), with which we can make inference regarding a given quantile.
### Mediation Effects
With additional assumptions (i.e., sequential ignorability [@imai2010general; @bullock2011mediation]), we can examine the mechanism of the treatment on the outcome.
Under the causal framework,
- the indirect effect of treatment via a mediator is called average causal mediation effect (ACME)
- the direct effect of treatment on outcome is the average direct effect (ADE)
More in the [Mediation] Section \@ref(mediation)
### Log-odds Treatment Effects
For binary outcome variable, we might be interested in the log-odds of success. See [@freedman2008randomization] on how to estimate a consistent causal effect.
Alternatively, attributable effects [@rosenbaum2002attributing] can also be appropriate for binary outcome.